19. ETHICS
© Roland O. Watson 2001-3
The last chapter
ended with the question of what values we would like our society to have. But
this, on the face of it, is not as difficult as it sounds. The values that we
seek are known as ethics, or at least they start with and derive from ethics.
For example, a number of positive values, including honesty, and patience and
tolerance, and a love of nature, have already been referred to throughout this
book. However, it is important to note that the existence of ethics presumes
that we have free will; that we have a choice in how we behave. If we are wholly
determined, then they do not exist. But, given the many arguments I have made,
I will assume that we do have free will, and therefore that we can have ethics.
Viewed simply, ethics are behavioral screens. They are a set of principles
(not tactics!) to guide your behavior in all possible situations. This begins
with taking responsibility for your actions and their consequences. In other
words, before you do something you should ask yourself what the consequences
will be. Will your behavior harm other people in some way, or the environment,
or even your culture or nation? (Politicians, take note!) Your first concern
should not always be to satisfy yourself (although there are personal ethics,
such as to make the most of your life). In this way ethics function as a check
on, as a defense against, our innate human selfishness.
We saw before that the types of problems which people cause have occurred again
and again throughout history, and we also reviewed the many different types
and sources of our bad behavior. To the extent that this behavior can be controlled,
the means by which this will be achieved will be ethics (not prisons!).
However, human society is not now, and quite possibly has never truly been,
ethical. The question is, why is this the case, and the answer is that these
different unethical behaviors have passed the test of time. They have passed
the evolutionary test, and been selected as the fittest to survive. In other
words, they work! Ruthlessness and selfishness are effective!
Im a thief.
Im a liar.
Theres a chance I sing in the choir.
- Do the Evolution, Pearl Jam
There are many challenges with ethics, and of these the greatest is that they
seek to alter behavior that has proven itself in the context of traditional
human circumstances. We come from, and in many ways still inhabit, the world
of kill or be killed. Because of this, we have the ethics of wild animals, which
has been referred to as Natural Law. In this world self-interest is the
only ideal, and in the pursuit of self-interest anything goes. There is no such
thing as good or evil, at least in a broader social context, or as such terms
might relate to anything we do. They only exist to describe things other
people do and their impact relative to us; what is good or bad for us.
But humans, in a very important sense, are no longer wild animals. We have been
able to rise above our genetic programming. We have a conscience, although it
is of course a complicated question where it comes from. (Again, like anything
human, it is derived in part from reason, will and education, and in part from
form, particularly social form.) Because of this we are in limbo, between natural
law and a more civilized system, with some other basis.
Also, once again, it is not as if this has not been recognized. People throughout
the ages have been trying to construct such an alternative basis. The starting
point in this search has been our existential condition. The unfathomability
of the universe and the certainty of death are in fact the logical foundations
of natural law. If there is no way we can know if there is an overriding purpose
to our existence, there would appear to be no way, no fundamental way, to judge
our behavior. (Conversely, if we knew what our purpose was, we could easily
- presumably - tailor our behavior to satisfy it.) The problem is that without
such a foundation everything inexorably leads to a subjectivist, i.e., supportive
of personal selfishness, conclusion. If there is no overall purpose, then your
existential goal reduces to your purpose, whatever you choose it to be.
However, we have a need for ethics. We are social animals, and there
have to be tradeoffs and compromises between people. We cannot get everything
that we want. We therefore need guidelines that will tell us how to act when
we are confronted with such tradeoffs, and more generally in all social interactions.
For instance, there is a tradeoff between freedom and equality. We want both,
but if we focus on equality then we have to give up a few freedoms, although
fortunately these are very few, and largely unethical, i.e., the freedom to
kill other people. On the other hand, if we focus on freedom, including the
freedom to compete, win and conquer, which traditionally has been the case,
we now understand that this means we will be unable to achieve real equality.
Also, whenever possible, we want to design our guidelines such that we avoid
what is known as zero-sum. This is where, when one person wins,
or gets what he or she wants, another person - at least one - necessarily does
not. Therefore, an underlying ethic of cooperation, where everyone gets some
of what they want, is better than competition, where one person gets everything
and the others get nothing at all.
Lastly, we have a crucial ethical need regarding our responsibility for the
planet. We must manage our behavior so we reduce and then reverse the environmental
problems that we create.
The foremost, or at least the first, of the alternatives to natural law are
ethical systems based on religion. Most religions do not in fact accept the
above contention of universal unknowability. To them, universal and human purpose
is known, and human behavior is regulated by Gods Law. However,
it turns out that if you look at the history of human religious traditions,
there have actually been two different types of ethical systems that have been
forwarded. The first is that to do right, you must follow Gods Law - as
revealed by prophets and saviors - or be punished. The second is that God
is Life is Truth, and that the ethic of life therefore is to understand
and assist it. It is notable that the first system has a negative component,
of punishment (although there is also the promise of salvation), while the second
is wholly positive. The first also tends to dogma and inflexibility: the Word
of God necessarily is perfect, and therefore can never be changed. On the
other hand, the second encourages education, and allows for the revision of
views as appropriate, and it has also led to a demonstrable reduction in suffering,
hence it has had a uniformly positive consequence.
(It of course gets much more complicated than this. There are many different
consequences of religious ethical systems, both positive and negative, and these
are examined in detail in the Religion chapter.)
The next basis for ethics derives from our social circumstances, but there are
a number of different, and divergent, elements of this. The first, which is
usually positive, is the ethical standard implied, and taught, by our mothers
care for us as an infant, and more broadly from the lifelong support we receive
from our family. Our parents and family help us, and we accept this as natural,
and by extension we consider it normal to help other people as well. Indeed,
you could almost consider this innate, particularly since it, at least the first
part - motherly care - also occurs with many other species of life.
The problem is: this is countered and in many cases overcome by either an instinct
or a need to compete with other people. I would argue that this in fact represents
a need, and even then that it exists only in some circumstances. When resources
are abundant, communities of many species, including humans, have shown no desire
to compete at all, and instead share and cooperate. What we term the competitive
instinct arises only in situations with limited resources and, as we have seen,
when it is fueled by social forms.
Indeed, you could ask the question: would you rather enjoy a sociable cup of
tea with someone, or fight them to death? Absent all social conditioning, consistently
choosing one or the other would constitute an innate ethic. Of course, it is
impossible to escape all social conditioning, so the choice cannot be made (although
I would hope it is the former). But, the fact that people regularly do not choose
tea over a fight - cooperation over competition - clearly reflects social conditioning.
However, there are situations where competition does appear to be ingrained,
such as between siblings for food and parental affection. In such cases, social
conditioning reinforces this competition. Also, both cooperation and competition,
and conditioning, reflect the continual struggle that is part of life. To repeat
the above point, in situations of abundant resources we regularly choose cooperation
over competition. But in situations where the resources are limited, we get
so caught up in the struggle that we do not even see that the first alternative,
the cup of tea, or cooperation, sharing and peace, is available. This begs the
question: how and when will we ever learn that this is an option?
This difficulty, our continued attachment to natural law, leads to the next
means by which society takes a role in our ethics. Society often acts as if
we are primitive animals that need to be controlled. And this, of course, is
a restatement of the challenge. Can we develop and rise above our history as
selfish animals, or do we need society in this way? Is this in fact its ultimate
purpose: to control us?
I hope not.
Also, I want to emphasize that this view is in many ways a modern development.
Human societies throughout the ages have always originated, arbitrated and enforced
different ethics, morals and values. And, they will always do this: it is actually
their most fundamental role. The key to the difference between traditional and
modern is in the interpretation, i.e., humans can be viewed positively or negatively.
Traditional societies usually took the former view. They rarely tried to control
or even contain us, just manage us so that we functioned more effectively as
a group. Modern society, on the other hand, definitely leans towards the negative
view, and the control and containment.
We should not overstate the distinction between traditional and modern, though.
In many cases traditional societies were, and are, worse than their modern counterparts:
they are still governed by natural law. For example, in many developing countries,
particularly if you live in a village or town in a rural area, if a crime is
perpetrated against you or your family (or even if you just become aware of
some other crime), you cannot go to the police. The police will not
arrest and imprison the criminal. Instead, they will find them, and then extract
a bribe from them and also quite possibly inform on you. This means there is
a high probability that the criminal will come after you, and try to kill you.
In this system you have no legal recourse, and there is no justice.
Your only option is the option that exists under natural law, or the domination
of the strong over the weak. You can try to kill the criminal yourself, or hire
someone else to do it. (Such an action was the only check on early despots.)
But, if you do this, you will probably have to kill their entire family as well,
to forestall the possibility of revenge. However, for most people this is not
an option, either ethically - they wont kill another person, or practically
- they cant get access to a gun, or they dont have the funds to
pay an assassin. So, again, there is no recourse at all. Of course, even if
you could get justice, this would likely plant the seed for a long-term
conflict, such as a blood feud. It is therefore no wonder that there are still
so many such conflicts in progress around the world.
(Also, it is interesting that in some traditional societies everyone
is on their own level. Anytime two people meet, they appraise each other:
who is superior and who is inferior. But this is the same thing that dogs do,
and many other animals as well. It is in fact as far from a system of equality
as it is possible to get.)
Within a society ethical promulgation is the responsibility of its social institutions.
And, as we have seen, we have moved from a world of traditional communities,
where such institutions (sometimes) conveyed positive messages in support of
the social group, to the modern world, where they ignore the welfare of the
general public and concentrate instead only on themselves. Also, different institutions
have always generated different values, but particularly in the modern world
these often conflict, and they regularly are unethical. Through this we can
see that social ethics have evolved. The dominant ethics of society nowadays
are the ethics of the leaders of our social institutions, of politicians, business
executives, press barons, evangelists and, of course, the values of Hollywood.
All of these are clearly designed to serve their interests, to the detriment
of ours.
One other consequence of this general state of affairs is the prevalence of
ethical confusion. With so many different, and competing, and conflicting values
out there, it is difficult to know what, and whom, to believe. For instance,
you may not think that you, personally, have an ethic, but you do, even though
it likely has many contradictory elements. Your ethic is based on your own reasoned
moral development, as furthered by your education. It is the set of principles
that you have adopted by choice, coupled with the values (good form) that you
have learned from your family and society. However, all of this has also been
combined with, and subverted by, the values that are inherent in the sources
of bad behavioral form to which you have been exposed.
For most people, what results is an ethical hodgepodge or mishmash. And this
is what causes the confusion, such as over how to act in a given situation.
In addition, this confusion causes us to feel as if life itself is in some way
contradictory. All of this affects our behavior, makes it less than rational,
and also our self-view: it assaults our self-esteem.
Everyone needs an ethical system which they can call their own: one that is
reasonable, which is based on education and experience, and which is internally
consistent and applicable in all situations. But, in the modern world, few of
us have one. Also, in this way we can see that an ethic is more than just rules
of behavior; it actually constitutes a philosophy of life. We need ethics, this
philosophy, to make sense of life and to make the best of our life; and also
for our role as part of society, to guide us to make the best tradeoffs and
compromises between the competing needs of different individuals.
In summary, society can no longer be trusted for moral guidance. We therefore
need a new ethical basis. And, it turns out that this basis is the same as the
solution to the failure of our social checks and balances: it is us. We must
now find our ethics, somehow, on our own, as individuals. The question is: how
can we possibly do this without falling prey to subjectivism and selfishness?
However, as difficult as this might seem, I guarantee that it is possible. We
saw earlier that one of the implications of the principle of human equality
is that we can all be heros. If this is the case, and it certainly is, it means
we can all be ethical as well.
Another perspective on innate ethics is that at birth we inhabit an ethical
vacuum. Other than crawling to our mother for food and warmth, and perhaps jostling
with our brothers and sisters in the process, we have no sense whatsoever of
how to behave. We have only a fundamental motivation to live, and the rest of
our behavior is necessarily shaped by environmental and genetic influences,
which can easily lead it to go off in unethical directions. To counter this
we need a basis as individuals for making behavioral choices, and the options
that are available to us are reason and emotion, i.e., to do what we think we
should do or what we want to do.
In considering these I will start with emotion, since it has two fundamental
flaws. The first is that it is too closely aligned with our self-interest: it
makes us prey to our innate selfishness, and causes us to devalue the interests
of others. Also, it is by definition out of our (rational) control, and therefore
is subject to great volatility. For example, love is probably the best and the
highest of our emotions. But when it is not reciprocated, this causes discomfort.
Discomfort in turn causes dissatisfaction, which itself readily leads to discontent,
and then resentment, and anger, and hate. Without reason to temper our emotion,
it can easily lead to extremes, particularly divisive and destructive extremes.
Put in another context, earlier I touted the benefits of impulsiveness as a
means to effect personal change. But without reason as a guide, we would be
equally prone to follow our unethical impulses as well as our good ones.
But, there are problems with reason as well. Relying on reason to too great
an extent tends to lead one towards asceticism and away from satisfying, and
ethical, passions. Life is passionate, and this should not be renounced. The
art of life is to use your reason to shape it, to construct an ethical guide
for it, but to use your emotion - your spontaneity - to live it. Viewed another
way, you want to temper your reason with your emotion: sometimes you follow
your mind, but other times you follow your heart. Moreover, you also want to
temper both with the benefits of your experience. By doing this you will make
use of all of your strengths, abilities and resources as you pursue the greatest
opportunity of all, which is life.
To expand this description, you should use your reason to further your formal
education (book and school) and for spiritual or philosophical speculation,
to preserve the planet, and to live in peace. You should use your emotion to
have fun, to enjoy the most simple satisfactions of life all the way through
to its most exhilarating and outrageous moments. Also, you should use both as
guides in your relationships with other people. Finally, you should use your
experience to oversee this entire process: as time goes by to get better and
better at the art of living your life.
In this way, it is possible to make value judgments without recourse to God,
and in the face of the subjectivism that is implied by the ant-farm analogy.
This type of ethical system is conscience. Of course, developing and applying
it will be a great challenge, and many people, at least in some circumstances,
will fail: they will act unethically.
The problem is, human nature, or human behavior, depends on the circumstances.
In good circumstances it is easy to be ethical, and to have great humanity.
In bad circumstances, and todays world in general - dominated by institutions
and ridden as it is with their form - is bad, it is much more difficult. People
are compelled to self-protection, to do whatever they must to survive. The greatest
challenge of all, again, the real test of humanity, is to retain our ethics
in such circumstances. Of course, many, many individuals have already proven
through their actions that this is possible. Only time will tell if we can prove
it as a species, if using our reason, emotion and experience, but mainly our
reason tempered with experience, we can learn that this option is available
and adopt it species-wide.
There are many other ethical challenges as well, which we will review later
in this chapter and in the last two parts of the book. One of them, though,
which is dealing with anger, both your own and the anger of others, is worth
some consideration here. This is because anger underlies and perpetuates so
many of our seemingly unresolvable problems.
We all get involved in a moment of emotion, and then we cannot get
out.
- The Quiet American, Graham Greene, Penguin, page 152
For most people ethics depend on the situation. In other words, they practice
what are known as relativistic ethics. They make up ethics on the spot,
to fit the situation, to satisfy their personal selfishness. But we are seeking
ethics that are firm, that are general principles, based on reason, and which
guard against our selfishness. However, in another, deeper sense, ethics are
situation-dependent. This is because all situations are different, even unique.
You will have to decide for yourself how to apply your ethics in many
different situations. For instance, it is easy to accept the golden rule, but
does its converse also apply: do unto others as they have already done unto
you? If someone takes advantage of you, are you justified in seeking revenge?
Do two wrongs make a right? There is often a fine line between justice and revenge,
and how you respond should always depend on the specific circumstances.
Anger is an extremely complex subject. This is because it can be both legitimate
and not. If someone causes you harm, you are completely justified in being angry
about it. Indeed, you would be a fool not to be.
In such cases anger is an expression of reason. And this anger should be resolved;
you should obtain justice for your injury. On the other hand, such anger can
easily get out of control: the emotion may take over with the consequence that
reason is left behind. In most cases this would be wrong: it would lead not
to justice but to revenge. However, this is not true in all cases. Even irrational,
uncontrollable anger, and anger leading to violence, is justified in a few circumstances,
such as when you are defending yourself or your family from attack. (It is in
these circumstances that anger has proven its evolutionary merit.)
But, because anger is such a volatile emotion, and also because it gives you
such a sense of power, it is also easily abused. For example, appeals to anger,
like the creation of fear, are a regular tactic of behavioral form. Sources
of form manipulate us to be angry about something, using rhetoric and not logic,
and then get us to act so as to suit their purposes.
Also, there are risks even in the application of legitimate anger, as is seen
clearly in the world of activism. Activists are legitimately angry about social
and environmental problems, and they want to do something about them. And in
general, they have three choices. The first is to use reason to educate people,
particularly the people who create the problems, to alter their behavior. Secondly,
they can convey this anger, and use it to energize an opposition. And this is
to use anger as a good form, since it is reasonable and not directed
to achieving a personally selfish end. Such a use is commonly seen at demonstrations
in the leading of group chants, and also in activist literature. However, it
is form, and the recipients of it, lacking the tempering reason of the advocates,
may easily be inclined to express their anger without limit. And through this
even good anger can end up having the same effects as bad anger (which
is the last option but really not an option at all), which is anger motivated
wholly by selfish ends, and used to inspire mobs to form and to riot and wreak
havoc.
Put simply, when you are emotionally involved your reason is clouded. And, it
is easy to make mistakes. Also, even if your reason stays intact, other people
may be swayed. This is why reason is far preferable as a motivator to good form,
including legitimate anger.
But, in any case, you cannot outlaw anger. What I am trying to say is that it
represents one of the clearest and most tangible examples of the real world
problems that our ethics must overcome, and also that any attempts to use it
in solving these problems are highly risky and may easily go astray.
Now, to close the chapter I will briefly consider some basic ethics regarding
your relationships with:
- yourself
- other people
- social institutions
- the planet, and other forms of life
As to ethics for yourself, we have already covered these extensively under personal
development, including the two fundamental goals to learn about and experience
life, and to help other people and species. Also, a number of additional guidelines
for individuals are given in the Your Future chapter in the final part of the
book.
For your relationships with other people, the basic ethic is to show respect,
both of them as individuals and of their cultures. You should accept other people
as they are, not try to impose your own form on them. However, there are two
distinctions that must be made when applying this ethic. The first is that you
should not tolerate intolerance, or prejudice, or primitive and savage behavior.
When in Rome, you are not always obliged to do as the Romans do. In this regard,
the real challenge is not to control your own behavior, but to decide what your
response to the intolerance should be. In some cases passive nonacceptance,
such as disinterest, will be called for, but in others outright rejection, even
intervention, will be appropriate. (This is regularly the motivation for activism.)
You will have to use your will, your reason, but also with some allowance for
your emotion - for legitimate anger - to decide.
Related to this is the idea that it is itself unethical to support others who
are unethical. We have already seen an example of this with police forces, which
refuse to bring bad cops to justice. In general, this ethical challenge most
commonly applies to employees of institutions who discover cases of institutional
wrongdoing. Such wrongdoings must be revealed, perhaps anonymously, as to the
press, or at least protested. Of course, it can get much more difficult than
this, as for a family member who becomes aware of the misdeeds of another, such
as by a mother of her son. The appropriate behavior in such cases will depend
on the specific circumstances, on the individuals and the misdeeds involved.
But at a minimum there should be communication within the family and, to the
greatest extent possible, and using reason and perhaps even threats, the unethical
individual should be persuaded to desist from his or her actions. (A recent
public example of such a situation was David Kaczynski turning his brother Ted
into the police, without confronting him first. This was a curious, and in a
way unethical - even cowardly - choice.)
To continue, the ethic of having respect will also lead you away from causing
harm. And, regarding this, you should try to live such that you do not injure
anyone, in the broadest sense of the phrase (anyone includes other
species). Also, I realize that at times, such as in love affairs, this will
be impossible.
This in turn, along with the previous discussion of anger, raises the question
of forgiveness. When, or for what, should you forgive someone? I would argue
that anything can and should be forgiven, with two conditions, the first
of which is absolutely essential. Justice must be served, the consequences of
the action must be paid, so there must be punishment in those cases where there
is a real misdeed. In addition, forgiveness should be granted when remorse for
the misdeed is given. The question is, what if this remorse in not forthcoming?
Another way to look at this is to recognize that forgiveness is the opposite
of revenge, and also that neither of them exist in natural law. They are largely
the province of humans. Revenge and torture are humanity at its worst. Forgiving
someone, even someone who has not expressed remorse (but who has received justice),
is humanity at its best. Forgiving someone a misdeed is the most difficult thing
a person can do. It is perhaps the most challenging ethical test of all.
The next ethic to consider, or reconsider, is the issue of negativity. One aspect
of form, which can yield either a positive or a negative result, is that you
(generally) get what you ask for. What this means is that if you want people
to be good, they will be: if you give them this option, they will usually take
it. But if you do not want people to be good, or even if you just presume that
they will not be, then they wont. This is bad form, and modern social
institutions are guilty of it all the time. They presume that we will be bad,
so we fulfill their expectations.
At a deeper level, negativity and positivity function as feedback
mechanisms, further examples of the phenomenon that as you change it, it
changes you. For positivity:
- If I treat you nice, you like it and are probably nice to me in return.
- If I continue to treat you nice, you come to expect it, and you also form
the pattern of being nice to me.
- Moreover, you incorporate what you have learned from your interactions with
me into your behavior with other people. You tend to be positive with them,
and they in turn are positive with you.
Therefore, to the extent that we want to construct good relationships with other
people, and a better society, we have to learn to treat each other positively.
More than anything, you should do your best not to be negative with people who
are trying to be good. You should not let any of your own selfish concerns get
in the way of their trying to be ethical.
My last comment on ethics regarding other people has to do with what are known
as human rights. In this book I argue that humans have rights, innate
rights that exist or which accrue to us merely because we are alive, and that
we - as activists - should work to see that they are extended to everyone, everywhere.
Now, I want to look at this another way. I want to question it, and even refute
it.
In life, in a very important sense, there is no such thing as a right. Rights
exist only insofar as they are earned. A right without this is the same as a
consequence without an associated action. Indeed, not having rights, rights
that you are supposed to have, again, makes you in some way a victim.
In concept, the rights to freedom, and equality, to food and water, etc., appear
so obvious that they can almost be taken for granted. But in practice, it is
a different story. A right that is not won, and defended, is nothing. If it
does not exist now, it never will, and if it does exist, it could easily, perhaps
inevitably, be taken away.
Rights, as a concept, while self-evident, constitute a weak and even dangerous
portrayal. Arguing for human rights may well not achieve the intended effect.
Rather, a more accurate formulation is that such rights are goals, or needs.
To the extent that we can only survive if our needs are met and our goals are
fulfilled, so it is with rights. We can only survive if we have them.
Do children have rights? Only if adults fight to win them, and defend them.
Does the environment, and do other species, have rights? Again, only if we win
and defend them.
Rights are not entitlements. They are goals and needs. Nothing in nature is
free. Life entails no such gift (other than its creation). The United Nations
Declaration of Human Rights is a statement of goals, and it should be recognized
and used as such.
As to ethics regarding our relationships with society and social institutions,
on your own and with others you should work to confront their modern form, and
get them to refocus their efforts from satisfying their needs to once again
serving ours. And, if you are employed in such an institution, you should consider
the specific comments for such individuals that I made earlier in the Fighting
Form chapter. Also, in order to guide our behavior towards society we need a
clearer idea of what we want the nature of our society to be, and to this end
a statement of our social goals is given in the Economics and Development chapter.
Lastly, regarding our relationship with the planet and other species of life,
the following quote, from a sign at the entrance to Yala National Park in southern
Sri Lanka, captures it best.
Through these gates you enter a protected area. The animals, birds,
trees, the water, the breeze on your face and every grain of sand, are gifts
that nature has passed on to you through your ancestors so that you may survive.
These gifts are sacred and should be respected. Whisper a silent prayer as you
pass through for the protection of wilderness around you and ensure that what
you see and feel is passed on to the unborn generations to come.
This should clearly be our approach to all of the worlds ecosystems and
species, not just to Yala!
We should - we must - learn to respect the rights - the goals and needs - of
other species, instead of selfishly caring only about our own. The rest of the
life on earth has been caught in a trap by our rapid population growth and voracious
appetite. The seemingly unstoppable evolutionary process of increasing diversity,
which has been underway for billions of years, and which is responsible for
the phenomenal natural beauty of the planet, has effectively been reversed.
All of the species that have suffered need a respite from our pressure. Indeed,
they need our assistance, so they can quickly regenerate themselves.
In an ideal world, and in the world we must, and will, create, the entire planet
would - it will - be turned into a park. By this I mean that massive expanses
of natural habitat will be preserved, and restored, and allowed to be subject
only to the forces of natural law and the patterns of natural evolution, i.e.,
without any human tampering or interference. The means to this end will be environmental
activism, voluntary control of our population and consumption, and well-reasoned
land, agricultural, industrial and technology planning.
Also, as this says, nature itself clearly should be left subject to natural
law. We, because of our abilities, need our own ethic: one based on those abilities
- on reason and not selfishness. But this does not mean that we have the right
to alter the ethics of other species or to apply the manipulative abilities
that derive from our reason to them, for instance, to shape their behavior (or
genes).
The lifeline of our planet, of any planet that bears life, is a string of species.
Our lifeline, our string, is now some three billion years old, and both hopefully
and likely it will continue for another such period. Therefore, any species
in such an immense string is, by definition, no better than any other. Each
did their job as a species: each stayed alive long enough to evolve. (Even those
species which failed to evolve served a purpose, by forming part of the overall
ecology and therefore, directly or indirectly, supporting those which did.)
Currently, we may be the most well adapted species on earth, meaning with the
best chance to survive and evolve, or we may not. It is impossible to say with
certainty. Hopefully, many, many species - millions of them - also are sufficiently
well adapted to survive and evolve. And, to the extent that they are, there
is no possibility of judgment between us and them. Indeed, other lines may prove
to be more durable, over the long-term, for whatever reasons. They will ultimately
be the links, the right links, that lead life forward, which in fact
makes them better.
But, even if we do prove to be the most well adapted, you cannot even say that
we are the best at this moment, i.e., until we hand over to our successors.
We could actually prove to be the best by taking away - by destroying - the
ability of other species to adapt and evolve, by taking away their lives, which
in a sense - certainly to them - actually makes us the worst.
It is of course impossible to refrain from killing other things, even if you
are a vegan and shun animal products entirely. Your body kills organisms, automatically,
as they invade it for their own ends. Parasites, viruses and bacteria, all must
be fought off continually by your bodys defense system, or you will die.
But these organisms are alive, too, and they also are only trying to live. Life,
for all living creatures, is a struggle in which survival requires that
other life must die.
We saw that humans in their perspectives on nature have a bias. We ignore this
struggle, but view its results as beautiful. But nature can be viewed as beautiful
in another way as well. Plants, of course, are beautiful from our traditional
aesthetic perspective, which is sensory, in their design and color and grace.
And plants are also beautiful because they live a relatively peaceful existence.
There may be tremendous competition between them for space, but their actual
survival involves little death. It is largely a process of photosynthesis and
the conversion of inorganic matter. So too it is with butterflies and other
pollinating insects, which to survive do not kill other life; instead, they
help spread it.
But all higher or more complex life (life with a central nervous system and
self-consciousness) kills other living things to survive all the time, including,
if not (for some species) predominantly, other higher life. The different species
of life can in fact be categorized by the amount, and the complexity, of the
other life that they kill. But, and here is the beauty, this is not in itself
horrible, or even unethical. It simply is. It cannot be judged for, again, what
measure could be used? (Plants are better than animals? Butterflies are better
than plants?) It is the natural rhythm, the natural symphony, of existence.
And we are part of it, too. To say that life is not beautiful, but that it is
ugly, is to say that we are ugly, too.
But we are not ugly. We sense, and we know, that life, including the creativity
that we bring to our own development, has beauty. Life has an innate beauty,
and also an applied beauty through this creativity. The extent or limit of the
beauty of life, though, it is impossible to know, but it clearly reaches extraordinary
levels. Indeed, what is the universe itself, a ballet of plants and animals,
of planets, stars and galaxies, if not beautiful?
However, even after considering all of this, we still need an ethic. Our goal
should therefore be to minimize our impact on other forms of life. We want to
kill less life, as little life as possible, particularly higher life, since
it can feel fear and pain. But, it is not just killing; we should also eliminate
any and all forms of mistreatment of other species of life.
It is in these types of cases that activists feel compelled to rise to the ethical
challenge. For example, if while walking down the street you see someone torturing
an animal, you should, and if you are ethical you will, intervene. But such
torture actually goes on all the time, and on a massive scale, behind closed
doors. In response to this animal rights activists do intervene, even though
this regularly requires civil disobedience, including trespass and even property
destruction, as of the instruments of torture.
Making medicines or vaccines to help humans is an ethical end, but torturing
and killing animals in the process is an unethical means. If we cannot find
a way to develop such treatments using only ethical means, then we simply should
not have them. We should use our will to deny ourselves. We should do our best
to survive without them, in other words, continue doing what we have already
done for two million years.
The same goes with fur. Being warm is an ethical end, but wearing the skin of
animals now that we have other and better alternatives, is not an ethical means
to accomplish this, not even if such animals can be harvested sustainably. You
do not farm tigers.
Is there any difference between killing flies, or mosquitos, or even parasites,
and killing people? In principle, no, there is not. A fly is part of a billion
year old lifeline just as much as you are. This therefore gives rise to the
great ethical challenge of application, since to survive you must kill. The
solution, as stated earlier, is that the only situation where you may justifiably
kill is in self-defense. But, is it a case of self-defense when drug companies
torture and slaughter thousands of animals to try to make drugs from which to
profit, including drugs that may save lives? They would certainly say so, but
this is self-serving, since as we will see later, their only concern
is to make a profit. Life-saving drugs are pursued only to the extent that this
can be accomplished profitably: the companys motivation is far from altruistic.
Therefore, life-saving medicines are ethical only if they have been developed
without animal exploitation. They are not ethical if such exploitation was used.
As to eating meat, and dairy products, and using animal products in general,
we must confront our carnivorous heritage, and also our bodys need for
protein. But vegans have proven that we can reduce our reliance on other non-plant
life greatly, if not completely. To the extent that you can follow their example,
this would be an admirable ethic to have. But am I going to demand that you
do this, and even seek to punish you for non-compliance? No. That would be form:
me telling you how to act. As unsatisfactory as it may be to some, ethics are
only guidelines, but as we have seen we will only install a better world, with
a sustainable equilibrium, if we can get there voluntarily.
I would implore you, though, not to patronize McDonalds and other such slaughterhouses.
Finding your own food in nature, for your own sustenance, as humans traditionally
have done, is one thing. Satisfying a socially prescribed need for obesity,
and supporting the institutions that promote it (and also hunting for sport),
is another.
And, it is not only fast food outlets: any meat that is available in a supermarket
likely came from a factory farm (an animal concentration camp). Organic foods,
including meats, where the animals living conditions are far superior
to life in a factory farm, are available. Of course, they may be more expensive,
but the solution to this is simple: eat organic, and eat less!
In conclusion, though, ethics, like life, are rarely easy. For instance, taking
the above to an extreme, some people would say that you should not kill mosquitoes,
simply because they may carry malarial or other parasites. (A few people
would even go so far as to say that the art of Bonsai is tree torture.) It is
better to let the mosquitoes bite you, and if you do catch malaria, then to
treat it. But then there is the question of the treatment: was it ethically
produced? Still better is to apply your reason and use a mosquito repellant.
But then the question becomes: what about the insecticide? It contains harmful
chemicals that pollute the ecosystem, and it was produced using destructive
technology that involved at a minimum the leveling of many specific environments
(the land for the factory, the land where the construction materials were mined
or cut, etc.). Such ethical challenges necessarily require complicated decisions
about consumption, and a further difficulty, which will be discussed later,
is the frequent unavailability of the information that you need to make them.